a2cf6aba85c816091641715567119ec7903063ac
[bitonic-mengthesis.git] / presentation.tex
1 \documentclass{beamer}
2 \usepackage[sc,slantedGreek]{mathpazo}
3
4
5 % Comment these out if you don't want a slide with just the
6 % part/section/subsection/subsubsection title:
7 \AtBeginPart{\frame{\partpage}}
8 \AtBeginSection{\frame{\sectionpage}}
9 \AtBeginSubsection{\frame{\subsectionpage}}
10 \AtBeginSubsubsection{\frame{\subsubsectionpage}}
11 \beamertemplatenavigationsymbolsempty
12
13 \usepackage{centernot}
14 \usepackage{cancel}
15
16 \setlength{\parindent}{0pt}
17 \setlength{\parskip}{6pt plus 2pt minus 1pt}
18 \setlength{\emergencystretch}{3em}  % prevent overfull lines
19 \setcounter{secnumdepth}{0}
20
21 \usepackage[english]{babel}
22 \usepackage[conor]{agda}
23 \renewcommand{\AgdaKeywordFontStyle}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathrm{\underline{#1}}}}
24 \renewcommand{\AgdaFunction}[1]{\textbf{\textcolor{AgdaFunction}{#1}}}
25 \renewcommand{\AgdaField}{\AgdaFunction}
26 % \definecolor{AgdaBound} {HTML}{000000}
27 \definecolor{AgdaHole} {HTML} {FFFF33}
28
29 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{9665}{\ensuremath{\lhd}}
30 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{964}{\ensuremath{\tau}}
31 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{963}{\ensuremath{\sigma}}
32 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{915}{\ensuremath{\Gamma}}
33 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{8799}{\ensuremath{\stackrel{?}{=}}}
34 \DeclareUnicodeCharacter{9655}{\ensuremath{\rhd}}
35
36 \newcommand{\mysmall}{}
37 \newcommand{\mysyn}{\AgdaKeyword}
38 \newcommand{\mytyc}[1]{\textup{\AgdaDatatype{#1}}}
39 \newcommand{\mydc}[1]{\textup{\AgdaInductiveConstructor{#1}}}
40 \newcommand{\myfld}[1]{\textup{\AgdaField{#1}}}
41 \newcommand{\myfun}[1]{\textup{\AgdaFunction{#1}}}
42 \newcommand{\myb}[1]{\AgdaBound{$#1$}}
43 \newcommand{\myfield}{\AgdaField}
44 \newcommand{\myind}{\AgdaIndent}
45 \newcommand{\mykant}{{\rmfamily\scshape Bertus}}
46 \newcommand{\mysynel}[1]{#1}
47 \newcommand{\myse}{\mysynel}
48 \newcommand{\mytmsyn}{\langle t \rangle}
49 \newcommand{\mysp}{\ }
50 \newcommand{\myabs}[2]{\mydc{$\lambda$} #1 \mathrel{\mydc{$\mapsto$}} #2}
51 \newcommand{\myappsp}{\hspace{0.07cm}}
52 \newcommand{\myapp}[2]{#1 \myappsp #2}
53 \newcommand{\mysynsep}{\ \ |\ \ }
54 \newcommand{\myITE}[3]{\myfun{If}\, #1\, \myfun{Then}\, #2\, \myfun{Else}\, #3}
55 \newcommand{\mycumul}{\preceq}
56
57 \newcommand{\mydesc}[3]{
58   \noindent
59   \mbox{
60     \parbox{\textwidth}{
61       {\mysmall
62         \vspace{0.2cm}
63         \hfill \textup{\phantom{ygp}\textbf{#1}} $#2$
64         \framebox[\textwidth]{
65           \parbox{\textwidth}{
66             \vspace{0.1cm}
67             \centering{
68               #3
69             }
70             \vspace{0.2cm}
71           }
72         }
73         \vspace{0.2cm}
74       }
75     }
76   }
77 }
78
79 \newcommand{\mytmt}{\mysynel{t}}
80 \newcommand{\mytmm}{\mysynel{m}}
81 \newcommand{\mytmn}{\mysynel{n}}
82 \newcommand{\myred}{\leadsto}
83 \newcommand{\myredd}{\stackrel{*}{\leadsto}}
84 \newcommand{\myreddd}{\stackrel{*}{\reflectbox{$\leadsto$}}}
85 \newcommand{\mysub}[3]{#1[#3 / #2]}
86 \newcommand{\mytysyn}{\langle ty \rangle}
87 \newcommand{\mybasetys}{K}
88 \newcommand{\mybasety}[1]{B_{#1}}
89 \newcommand{\mytya}{\myse{A}}
90 \newcommand{\mytyb}{\myse{B}}
91 \newcommand{\mytycc}{\myse{C}}
92 \newcommand{\myarr}{\mathrel{\textcolor{AgdaDatatype}{\to}}}
93 \newcommand{\myprod}{\mathrel{\textcolor{AgdaDatatype}{\times}}}
94 \newcommand{\myctx}{\Gamma}
95 \newcommand{\myvalid}[1]{#1 \vdash \underline{\mathrm{valid}}}
96 \newcommand{\myjudd}[3]{#1 \vdash #2 : #3}
97 \newcommand{\myjud}[2]{\myjudd{\myctx}{#1}{#2}}
98 \newcommand{\myabss}[3]{\mydc{$\lambda$} #1 {:} #2 \mathrel{\mydc{$\mapsto$}} #3}
99 \newcommand{\mytt}{\mydc{$\langle\rangle$}}
100 \newcommand{\myunit}{\mytyc{Unit}}
101 \newcommand{\mypair}[2]{\mathopen{\mydc{$\langle$}}#1\mathpunct{\mydc{,}} #2\mathclose{\mydc{$\rangle$}}}
102 \newcommand{\myfst}{\myfld{fst}}
103 \newcommand{\mysnd}{\myfld{snd}}
104 \newcommand{\myconst}{\myse{c}}
105 \newcommand{\myemptyctx}{\varepsilon}
106 \newcommand{\myhole}{\AgdaHole}
107 \newcommand{\myfix}[3]{\mysyn{fix} \myappsp #1 {:} #2 \mapsto #3}
108 \newcommand{\mysum}{\mathbin{\textcolor{AgdaDatatype}{+}}}
109 \newcommand{\myleft}[1]{\mydc{left}_{#1}}
110 \newcommand{\myright}[1]{\mydc{right}_{#1}}
111 \newcommand{\myempty}{\mytyc{Empty}}
112 \newcommand{\mycase}[2]{\mathopen{\myfun{[}}#1\mathpunct{\myfun{,}} #2 \mathclose{\myfun{]}}}
113 \newcommand{\myabsurd}[1]{\myfun{absurd}_{#1}}
114 \newcommand{\myarg}{\_}
115 \newcommand{\myderivsp}{}
116 \newcommand{\myderivspp}{\vspace{0.3cm}}
117 \newcommand{\mytyp}{\mytyc{Type}}
118 \newcommand{\myneg}{\myfun{$\neg$}}
119 \newcommand{\myar}{\,}
120 \newcommand{\mybool}{\mytyc{Bool}}
121 \newcommand{\mytrue}{\mydc{true}}
122 \newcommand{\myfalse}{\mydc{false}}
123 \newcommand{\myitee}[5]{\myfun{if}\,#1 / {#2.#3}\,\myfun{then}\,#4\,\myfun{else}\,#5}
124 \newcommand{\mynat}{\mytyc{$\mathbb{N}$}}
125 \newcommand{\myrat}{\mytyc{$\mathbb{R}$}}
126 \newcommand{\myite}[3]{\myfun{if}\,#1\,\myfun{then}\,#2\,\myfun{else}\,#3}
127 \newcommand{\myfora}[3]{(#1 {:} #2) \myarr #3}
128 \newcommand{\myexi}[3]{(#1 {:} #2) \myprod #3}
129 \newcommand{\mypairr}[4]{\mathopen{\mydc{$\langle$}}#1\mathpunct{\mydc{,}} #4\mathclose{\mydc{$\rangle$}}_{#2{.}#3}}
130 \newcommand{\mynil}{\mydc{[]}}
131 \newcommand{\mycons}{\mathbin{\mydc{∷}}}
132 \newcommand{\myfoldr}{\myfun{foldr}}
133 \newcommand{\myw}[3]{\myapp{\myapp{\mytyc{W}}{(#1 {:} #2)}}{#3}}
134 \newcommand{\mynodee}{\mathbin{\mydc{$\lhd$}}}
135 \newcommand{\mynode}[2]{\mynodee_{#1.#2}}
136 \newcommand{\myrec}[4]{\myfun{rec}\,#1 / {#2.#3}\,\myfun{with}\,#4}
137 \newcommand{\mylub}{\sqcup}
138 \newcommand{\mydefeq}{\cong}
139 \newcommand{\myrefl}{\mydc{refl}}
140 \newcommand{\mypeq}{\mytyc{=}}
141 \newcommand{\myjeqq}{\myfun{$=$-elim}}
142 \newcommand{\myjeq}[3]{\myapp{\myapp{\myapp{\myjeqq}{#1}}{#2}}{#3}}
143 \newcommand{\mysubst}{\myfun{subst}}
144 \newcommand{\myprsyn}{\myse{prop}}
145 \newcommand{\myprdec}[1]{\mathopen{\mytyc{$\llbracket$}} #1 \mathclose{\mytyc{$\rrbracket$}}}
146 \newcommand{\myand}{\mathrel{\mytyc{$\wedge$}}}
147 \newcommand{\mybigand}{\mathrel{\mytyc{$\bigwedge$}}}
148 \newcommand{\myprfora}[3]{\forall #1 {:} #2.\, #3}
149 \newcommand{\myimpl}{\mathrel{\mytyc{$\Rightarrow$}}}
150 \newcommand{\mybot}{\mytyc{$\bot$}}
151 \newcommand{\mytop}{\mytyc{$\top$}}
152 \newcommand{\mycoe}{\myfun{coe}}
153 \newcommand{\mycoee}[4]{\myapp{\myapp{\myapp{\myapp{\mycoe}{#1}}{#2}}{#3}}{#4}}
154 \newcommand{\mycoh}{\myfun{coh}}
155 \newcommand{\mycohh}[4]{\myapp{\myapp{\myapp{\myapp{\mycoh}{#1}}{#2}}{#3}}{#4}}
156 \newcommand{\myjm}[4]{(#1 {:} #2) \mathrel{\mytyc{=}} (#3 {:} #4)}
157 \newcommand{\myeq}{\mathrel{\mytyc{=}}}
158 \newcommand{\myprop}{\mytyc{Prop}}
159 \newcommand{\mytmup}{\mytmsyn\uparrow}
160 \newcommand{\mydefs}{\Delta}
161 \newcommand{\mynf}{\Downarrow}
162 \newcommand{\myinff}[3]{#1 \vdash #2 \Uparrow #3}
163 \newcommand{\myinf}[2]{\myinff{\myctx}{#1}{#2}}
164 \newcommand{\mychkk}[3]{#1 \vdash #2 \Downarrow #3}
165 \newcommand{\mychk}[2]{\mychkk{\myctx}{#1}{#2}}
166 \newcommand{\myann}[2]{#1 : #2}
167 \newcommand{\mydeclsyn}{\myse{decl}}
168 \newcommand{\myval}[3]{#1 : #2 \mapsto #3}
169 \newcommand{\mypost}[2]{\mysyn{abstract}\ #1 : #2}
170 \newcommand{\myadt}[4]{\mysyn{data}\ #1 #2\ \mysyn{where}\ #3\{ #4 \}}
171 \newcommand{\myreco}[4]{\mysyn{record}\ #1 #2\ \mysyn{where}\ #3\{ #4 \}}
172 \newcommand{\myelabt}{\vdash}
173 \newcommand{\myelabf}{\rhd}
174 \newcommand{\myelab}[2]{\myctx \myelabt #1 \myelabf #2}
175 \newcommand{\mytele}{\Delta}
176 \newcommand{\mytelee}{\delta}
177 \newcommand{\mydcctx}{\Gamma}
178 \newcommand{\mynamesyn}{\myse{name}}
179 \newcommand{\myvec}{\overrightarrow}
180 \newcommand{\mymeta}{\textsc}
181 \newcommand{\myhyps}{\mymeta{hyps}}
182 \newcommand{\mycc}{;}
183 \newcommand{\myemptytele}{\varepsilon}
184 \newcommand{\mymetagoes}{\Longrightarrow}
185 % \newcommand{\mytesctx}{\
186 \newcommand{\mytelesyn}{\myse{telescope}}
187 \newcommand{\myrecs}{\mymeta{recs}}
188 \newcommand{\myle}{\mathrel{\lcfun{$\le$}}}
189 \newcommand{\mylet}{\mysyn{let}}
190 \newcommand{\myhead}{\mymeta{head}}
191 \newcommand{\mytake}{\mymeta{take}}
192 \newcommand{\myix}{\mymeta{ix}}
193 \newcommand{\myapply}{\mymeta{apply}}
194 \newcommand{\mydataty}{\mymeta{datatype}}
195 \newcommand{\myisreco}{\mymeta{record}}
196 \newcommand{\mydcsep}{\ |\ }
197 \newcommand{\mytree}{\mytyc{Tree}}
198 \newcommand{\myproj}[1]{\myfun{$\pi_{#1}$}}
199 \newcommand{\mysigma}{\mytyc{$\Sigma$}}
200 \newcommand{\mynegder}{\vspace{-0.3cm}}
201 \newcommand{\myquot}{\Uparrow}
202 \newcommand{\mynquot}{\, \Downarrow}
203 \newcommand{\mycanquot}{\ensuremath{\textsc{quote}{\Downarrow}}}
204 \newcommand{\myneuquot}{\ensuremath{\textsc{quote}{\Uparrow}}}
205 \newcommand{\mymetaguard}{\ |\ }
206 \newcommand{\mybox}{\Box}
207 \newcommand{\mytermi}[1]{\text{\texttt{#1}}}
208 \newcommand{\mysee}[1]{\langle\myse{#1}\rangle}
209 \newcommand{\mycomp}{\mathbin{\myfun{$\circ$}}}
210 \newcommand{\mylist}[1]{\mytyc{List}\myappsp #1}
211 \newcommand{\mylistt}[1]{\mathopen{\mydc{$[$}} #1 \mathclose{\mydc{$]$}}}
212 \newcommand{\myplus}{\mathbin{\myfun{$+$}}}
213 \newcommand{\mytimes}{\mathbin{\myfun{$*$}}}
214 \newcommand{\mysuc}{\mydc{suc}}
215 \newcommand{\myzero}{\mydc{zero}}
216
217 \renewcommand{\[}{\begin{equation*}}
218 \renewcommand{\]}{\end{equation*}}
219 \newcommand{\mymacol}[2]{\text{\textcolor{#1}{$#2$}}}
220
221 \title{\mykant: Implementing Observational Equality}
222 \author{Francesco Mazzoli \texttt{<fm2209@ic.ac.uk>}}
223 \date{June 2013}
224
225 \begin{document}
226 \frame{\titlepage}
227
228 \begin{frame}
229   \frametitle{\mykant?}
230
231   \mykant\ is an \emph{interactive theorem prover}/\emph{functional
232     programming language}, implemented in Haskell.
233
234   It is similar in scope to Agda or Coq, but with a more powerful notion
235   of \emph{equality}.
236
237   We have figured out theory of \mykant, and have a near-complete
238   implementation.
239 \end{frame}
240
241 \begin{frame}
242   \frametitle{Theorem provers are short-sighted}
243
244   Two functions dear to the Haskell practitioner:
245   \[
246   \begin{array}{@{}l}
247     \myfun{map} : (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{b}) \myarr \mylist{\myb{a}} \myarr \mylist{\myb{b}} \\
248       \begin{array}{@{}l@{\myappsp}c@{\myappsp}c@{\ }c@{\ }l}
249         \myfun{map} & \myb{f} & \mynil & = & \mynil \\
250         \myfun{map} & \myb{f} & (\myb{x} \mycons \myb{xs}) & = & \myapp{\myb{f}}{\myb{x}} \mycons \myfun{map} \myappsp \myb{f} \myappsp \myb{xs} \\
251       \end{array}
252       \\
253       \ \\
254     (\myfun{${\circ}$}) : (\myb{b} \myarr \myb{c}) \myarr (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{b}) \myarr (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{c}) \\
255     (\myb{f} \mathbin{\myfun{$\circ$}} \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{x} = \myapp{\myb{g}}{(\myapp{\myb{f}}{\myb{x}})}
256   \end{array}
257   \]
258 \end{frame}
259
260 \begin{frame}
261   \frametitle{Theorem provers are short-sighted}
262   $\myfun{map}$'s composition law states that:
263   \[
264     \forall \myb{f} {:} (\myb{b} \myarr \myb{c}), \myb{g} {:} (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{b}). \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{g} \myeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myb{f} \mycomp \myb{g})
265   \]
266   We can convince Coq or Agda that
267   \[
268     \forall \myb{f} {:} (\myb{b} \myarr \myb{c}), \myb{g} {:} (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{b}), \myb{l} {:} \mylist{\myb{a}}. (\myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{l} \myeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myb{f} \mycomp \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{l}    
269   \]
270   But we cannot get rid of the $\myb{l}$.  Why?
271 \end{frame}
272
273 \begin{frame}
274   \frametitle{\mykant\ and observational equality}
275
276   \emph{Observational} equality solves this and other annoyances.
277
278   \mykant\ is a system aiming at making observational equality more
279   usable.
280 \end{frame}
281
282 \begin{frame}
283   \frametitle{Theorem provers, dependent types}
284   \begin{center}
285     \Huge
286     types $\leftrightarrow$ propositions
287
288     programs $\leftrightarrow$ proofs
289   \end{center}
290 \end{frame}
291
292 \begin{frame}
293   \frametitle{Theorem provers, dependent types} First class types: we
294   can return them, have them as arguments, etc.
295   \[
296   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ \ \ }l}
297     \mysyn{data}\ \myempty & \text{No members.} \\
298     \mysyn{data}\ \myunit \mapsto \mytt & \text{One member.}
299   \end{array}
300   \]
301   $\myempty : \mytyp$, $\myunit : \mytyp$.
302
303   $\myunit$ is trivially inhabitable: it corresponds to $\top$ in
304   logic.
305   \[
306   \mytt : \myunit
307   \]
308   $\myempty$ is \emph{not} inhabitable: it corresponds to $\bot$.
309   \[
310   \myfun{absurd} : \myempty \myarr \myb{A}
311   \]
312 \end{frame}
313
314 \begin{frame}
315   \frametitle{Theorem provers, dependent types}
316   \[ \mysyn{data}\ \mylist{\myb{A}} \mapsto \mynil \mydcsep \myb{A} \mycons \mylist{\myb{A}} \]
317   We want to express a `non-emptiness' property for lists:
318   \[
319   \begin{array}{@{}l}
320     \myfun{non-empty} : \mylist{\myb{A}} \myarr \mytyp \\
321     \begin{array}{@{}l@{\myappsp}c@{\ }l}    
322     \myfun{non-empty} & \mynil & \mapsto \myempty \\
323     \myfun{non-empty} & (\myb{x} \mycons \myb{l}) & \mapsto \myunit
324     \end{array}
325   \end{array}
326   \]
327
328   A term of type $\myfun{non-empty} \myappsp \myb{l}$ represents a
329   \emph{proof} that $\myb{l}$ is indeed not empty.
330   \[
331   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ \ \ }l}
332     \text{Can't prove} & \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp \mynil \myred \myempty \\
333     \text{Trivial to prove}  & \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp(2 \mycons \mynil) \myred \myunit
334   \end{array}
335   \]
336 \end{frame}
337
338 \begin{frame}
339   \frametitle{Example: safe $\myfun{head}$ function}
340   \only<3>{We can eliminate the `empty list' case:}
341   \[
342   \begin{array}{@{}l}
343     \myfun{head} : \myfora{\myb{l}}{\mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A}}{ \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp\myb{l} \myarr \myb{A}} \\
344     \begin{array}{@{}l@{\myappsp}c@{\myappsp}c@{\ }c@{\ }l}
345       \myfun{head} & \mynil & \myb{p} & \mapsto & \only<1,2>{\myhole{?}}\only<3>{\myabsurd\myappsp\myb{p}} \\
346       \myfun{head} & (\myb{x} \mycons \myb{xs}) & \myb{p} & \mapsto & \myb{x}
347     \end{array}
348   \end{array}
349   \]
350
351   \only<1>{
352     The logic equivalent would be
353     \[
354     \forall \myb{l} {:} \mylist{\myb{A}}.\ \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp\myb{l} \myarr \myb{A}
355     \]
356     `For all non-empty lists of type $\myb{A}$, we can get an element of $\myb{A}$.'
357   }
358   \only<2>{
359   The type of $\myb{p}$ in the $\myhole{?}$ is $\myempty$, since
360   \[\myfun{non-empty}\myappsp\mynil \myred \myempty \]}
361   \only<3>{
362     Remember:
363     \[ \myfun{absurd} : \myempty \myarr \myb{A} \]
364   }
365 \end{frame}
366
367 \begin{frame}
368   \frametitle{How do we type check this thing?}
369   \[
370   \myfun{head} \myappsp (3 \mycons \mynil) : \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp(3 \mycons \mynil) \myarr \mynat
371   \]
372   Is it the case that
373   \[ \mytt : \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp(3 \mycons \mynil) \]
374   Or
375   \[ \myfun{head} \myappsp (3 \mycons \mynil) : \myunit \myarr \mynat \]
376
377   Yes: to typecheck, we reduce terms fully (to their \emph{normal} form)
378   before comparing:
379   \[
380   \begin{array}{@{}r@{\ }c@{\ }c@{\ }c@{\ }c@{\ }c@{\ }l}
381     \myunit & \myredd & \myunit & \mydefeq & \myunit & \myreddd & \myfun{non-empty}\myappsp(3 \mycons \mynil) \\
382     (\myabs{\myb{x}\, \myb{y}}{\myb{y}}) \myappsp \myunit \myappsp \myappsp \mynat & \myredd & \mynat & \mydefeq & \mynat & \myreddd & (\myabs{\myb{x}\, \myb{y}}{\myb{x}}) \myappsp \mynat \myappsp \myunit \\
383     & & & \vdots & & & 
384   \end{array}
385   \]
386   \[
387   \mydefeq\ \text{takes the name of \textbf{definitional equality}.}
388   \]
389 \end{frame}
390
391 \begin{frame}
392   \frametitle{Propositional equality} Using definitional equality, we
393   can give the user a type-level notion of term equality.
394   \[
395   (\myeq) : \myb{A} \myarr \myb{A} \myarr \mytyp\ \ \ \text{internalises equality \textbf{as a type}}
396   \]
397   We introduce members of $\myeq$ by reflexivity, for example
398   \[
399   \myrefl\myappsp5 : 5 \myeq 5
400   \]
401   But also
402   \[
403   \begin{array}{@{}l}
404   \myrefl\myappsp 5 : (3 + 2) \myeq (1 + 4)\text{, since}\\
405   (3 + 2) \myeq (1 + 4) \myredd 5 \myeq 5
406   \end{array}
407   \]
408   Then we can use a substitution law to derive other
409   laws---transitivity, congruence, etc.
410   \[ \myeq\ \text{takes the name of \textbf{propositional equality}} \]
411 \end{frame}
412
413 \begin{frame}
414 \frametitle{The problem with prop. equality}
415 Going back to $\myfun{map}$, we can prove that
416 \[    \forall \myb{f} {:} (\myb{b} \myarr \myb{c}), \myb{g} {:} (\myb{a} \myarr \myb{b}), \myb{l} {:} \mylist{\myb{a}}.\ (\myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{l} \myeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myb{f} \mycomp \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{l}    \]
417 Because
418 \[
419 (\myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{g})\myappsp \myb{l} \mydefeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myb{f} \mycomp \myb{g}) \myappsp \myb{l}
420 \]
421 By induction on $\myb{l}$.
422
423 Without the $\myb{l}$ we cannot compute, so we are stuck with
424 \[
425 \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myb{g} \not\mydefeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myb{f} \mycomp \myb{g})
426 \]
427 \end{frame}
428
429 \begin{frame}
430   \frametitle{Observational equality}
431
432   Instead of basing its equality on definitional equality, look at the
433   structure of the type to decide.
434
435   For functions this will mean that proving
436   \[
437     \myfun{map}\myappsp \myse{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myse{g} \myeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myse{f} \mycomp \myse{g})
438   \]
439   Will reduce to proving that
440   \[
441   (\myb{l} : \mylist{\myb{A}}) \myarr 
442     (\myfun{map}\myappsp \myse{f} \mycomp \myfun{map}\myappsp \myse{g})\myappsp\myb{l} \myeq \myfun{map}\myappsp (\myse{f} \mycomp \myse{g})\myappsp \myb{l}
443   \]
444   Which is what we want.  The interesting part is how to make the system
445   compute nicely.
446   
447   This extends to other structures (tuples, inductive types, \dots).
448   Moreover, if we can deem two \emph{types} equal, we can \emph{coerce}
449   values from one to the other.
450 \end{frame}
451
452 \begin{frame}
453   \begin{center}
454     {\huge \mykant' features}
455   \end{center}
456 \end{frame}
457
458 \begin{frame}
459   \frametitle{Inductive data}
460   \[
461   \mysyn{data}\ \mytyc{List}\myappsp (\myb{A} : \mytyp) \mapsto \mynil \mydcsep \myb{A} \mycons \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A}
462   \]
463   Each with an induction principle:
464   \[
465   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ }l}
466     \mytyc{List}.\myfun{elim} : & \AgdaComment{-{}- The property that we want to prove:} \\
467      & (\myb{P} : \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A} \myarr \mytyp) \myarr \\
468      & \AgdaComment{-{}- If it holds for the base case:} \\
469     & \myb{P} \myappsp \mynil \myarr \\
470     & \AgdaComment{-{}- And for the inductive step:} \\
471     & ((\myb{x} : \myb{A}) \myarr (\myb{l} : \mytyc{List}\myappsp \myb{A}) \myarr \myb{P} \myappsp \myb{l} \myarr \myb{P} \myappsp (\myb{x} \mycons \myb{l})) \myarr \\
472     & \AgdaComment{-{}- Then it holds for every list:} \\
473     & (\myb{l} : \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A}) \myarr \myb{P} \myappsp \myb{l}
474   \end{array}
475   \]
476   Induction is also computation, via structural recursion:
477   \[
478   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ }l}
479     \mytyc{List}.\myfun{elim} \myappsp \myse{P} \myappsp \myse{pn} \myappsp \myse{pc} \myappsp \mynil & \myred \myse{pn} \\
480     \mytyc{List}.\myfun{elim} \myappsp \myse{P} \myappsp \myse{pn} \myappsp \myse{pc} \myappsp (\mytmm \mycons \mytmn) & \myred \myse{pc} \myappsp \mytmm \myappsp \mytmn \myappsp (\mytyc{List}.\myfun{elim} \myappsp \myse{P} \myappsp \myse{pn} \myappsp \myse{ps} \myappsp \mytmt )
481   \end{array}
482   \]
483 \end{frame}
484
485 \begin{frame}
486   \frametitle{Dependent defined types} \emph{Unlike} Haskell, we can
487   have fields of a data constructor to depend on earlier fields:
488   \[
489   \begin{array}{@{}l}
490     \mysyn{record}\ \mytyc{Tuple}\myappsp(\myb{A} : \mytyp)\myappsp\myhole{$(\myb{B} : \myb{A} \myarr \mytyp)$} \mapsto \\
491     \myind{2}\mydc{tuple}\ \{ \myfun{fst} : \myb{A}, \myfun{snd} : \myb{B}\myappsp\myb{fst} \}
492   \end{array}
493   \]
494
495   The \emph{type} of the second element depends on the \emph{value} of
496   the first:
497   \[
498   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ }l}
499     \myfun{fst} & : \mytyc{Tuple}\myappsp\myb{A}\myappsp\myb{B} \myarr \myb{A} \\
500     \myfun{snd} & : (\myb{x} : \mytyc{Tuple}\myappsp\myb{A}\myappsp\myb{B}) \myarr \myb{B} \myappsp (\myfun{fst} \myappsp \myb{x})
501   \end{array}
502   \]
503   Where the projection's reduction rules are predictably
504   \[
505   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ }l}
506     \myfun{fst}\myappsp&(\mydc{tuple}\myappsp\mytmm\myappsp\mytmn) \myred \mytmm \\
507     \myfun{snd}\myappsp&(\mydc{tuple}\myappsp\mytmm\myappsp\mytmn) \myred \mytmn \\
508   \end{array}
509   \]
510 \end{frame}
511
512 \begin{frame}
513   \frametitle{Example: the type of even numbers}
514   For example we can define the type of even numbers:
515   % TODO fix
516   \[
517   \begin{array}{@{}l}
518     \myfun{even} : \mynat \myarr \mytyp \\
519     \begin{array}{@{}l@{\myappsp}c@{\ }l}
520       \myfun{even} & \myzero & \mapsto \myunit \\
521       \myfun{even} & (\mysuc \myappsp \myzero) & \mapsto \myempty \\
522       \myfun{even} & (\mysuc \myappsp (\mysuc \myappsp \myb{n})) & \mapsto \myfun{even} \myappsp \myb{n}
523     \end{array} \\
524     \ \\
525     \mytyc{Even} : \mytyp \\
526     \mytyc{Even} \mapsto \mytyc{Tuple}\ \mynat\ \myfun{even}
527   \end{array}
528   \]
529 \end{frame}
530
531 \begin{frame}
532   \frametitle{Type hierarchy}
533   \[\{\mynat, \mybool, \mytyc{List}\myappsp\mynat, \cdots\} : \mytyp\]
534   What is the type of $\mytyp$?
535   \[
536   \cancel{\mytyp : \mytyp}\ \ \ \text{\textbf{inconsistent}}
537   \]
538   Similar to Russel's paradox in na{\"i}ve set theory.
539
540   Instead, we have a hierarchy:
541   \[
542   \{\mynat, \mybool, \mytyc{List}\myappsp\mynat, \cdots\} : \mytyp_0 : \mytyp_1 : \cdots
543   \]
544   We talk of types in $\mytyp_0$ as `smaller' than types in $\mytyp_1$.
545 \end{frame}
546
547 \begin{frame}
548   \frametitle{Cumulativity and typical ambiguity}
549   Instead of:
550   \[ \mytyp_0 : \mytyp_1 \ \ \ \text{but}\ \ \ \mytyp_0 \centernot{:} \mytyp_2\]
551   We have a cumulative hierarchy, so that
552   \[ \mytyp_n : \mytyp_m \ \ \ \text{iff}\ \ \ n < m \]
553   For example
554   \[ \mynat : \mytyp_0\ \ \ \text{and}\ \ \ \mynat : \mytyp_1\ \ \ \text{and}\ \ \ \mynat : \mytyp_{50} \]
555
556   But in \mykant, you can forget about levels: the consistency is
557   checked automatically---a mechanised version of what Russell called
558   \emph{typical ambiguity}.
559 \end{frame}
560
561 \begin{frame}
562   \frametitle{Bidirectional type checking}
563   \[
564   \mysyn{data}\ \mytyc{List}\myappsp (\myb{A} : \mytyp) \mapsto \mydc{nil} \mydcsep \mydc{cons} \myappsp \myb{A}\myappsp (\mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A})
565   \]
566
567   With no type inference, we have explicit types for the constructors:
568   \[
569   \begin{array}{@{}l@{\ }l}
570     \mydc{nil} & : (\myb{A} : \mytyp) \myarr \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A} \\
571     \mydc{cons} &: (\myb{A} : \mytyp) \myarr \myb{A} \myarr \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A} \myarr \mytyc{List}\myappsp\myb{A}\\
572   \end{array}
573   \]
574   ...ugh:
575   \[
576   \mydc{cons}\myappsp \mynat\myappsp 1 \myappsp (\mydc{cons}\myappsp \mynat \myappsp 2 \myappsp (\mydc{cons}\myappsp \mynat \myappsp 3 \myappsp (\mydc{nil}\myappsp \mynat)))
577   \]
578   Instead, annotate terms and propagate the type:
579   \[
580   \mydc{cons}\myappsp 1 \myappsp (\mydc{cons}\myappsp 2 \myappsp (\mydc{cons} \myappsp 3 \myappsp \mydc{nil})) : \mytyc{List}\myappsp\mynat
581   \]
582   Conversely, when we use eliminators the type can be inferred.
583 \end{frame}
584
585 \begin{frame}
586   \frametitle{Bidirectional type checking}
587
588   This technique is known as \emph{bidirectional} type checking---some
589   terms get \emph{checked}, some terms \emph{infer} types.
590
591   Usually used for pre-defined types or core calculi, \mykant\ extends
592   to user-defined types.
593 \end{frame}
594
595 \begin{frame}
596   \frametitle{OTT + user defined types}
597
598   For each type, we need to:
599   \begin{itemize}
600   \item Describe when two types formed by the defined type constructors
601     are equal;
602     \[ \mylist{\mytya_1} \myeq \mylist{\mytya_2} \]
603   \item Describe when two values of the defined type are equal;
604     \[
605     \begin{array}{@{}c@{\ \ \ \ \ \ }c}
606       \mynil \myeq \mynil & \mynil \myeq \mytmm \mycons \mytmn \\
607       \mytmm \mycons \mytmn \myeq \mynil & \mytmm_1 \mycons \mytmn_1 \myeq \mytmm_2 \mycons \mytmn_2
608     \end{array}
609     \]
610   \item Describe how to transport values of the defined type.
611   \end{itemize}
612 \end{frame}
613
614 \begin{frame}
615   \frametitle{OTT + hierarchy}
616
617   Since equalities reduce to functions abstracting over various things,
618   we need to make sure that the hierarchy is respected.
619
620   For example we have that
621   \[
622   \begin{array}{@{}l}
623     (\myb{x_1} {:} \mytya_1) \myarr \mytyb_1 \myeq (\myb{x_2} {:} \mytya_2) \myarr \mytyb_2 \myred \\
624     \myind{2} \mytya_1 \myeq \mytya_2 \myand 
625     ((\myb{x_1} : \mytya_1) \myarr (\myb{x_2} : \mytya_2) \myarr \mytyb_1[\myb{x_1}] \myeq \mytyb_2[\myb{x_2}])
626   \end{array}
627   \]
628
629   Subtle point---I discovered a problem in the theory after
630   submitting... but I have a fix.
631 \end{frame}
632
633 \begin{frame}
634 \begin{center}
635 {\Huge Demo}
636 \end{center}
637 \end{frame}
638
639 \begin{frame}
640   \frametitle{Further work}
641
642   \begin{itemize}
643     \item Pattern matching and explicit recursion
644     \item More expressive data types
645     \item Inference via unification
646     \item Codata
647   \end{itemize}
648 \end{frame}
649
650 \begin{frame}
651 \begin{center}
652 {\Huge Questions?}
653 \end{center}
654 \end{frame}
655
656 \end{document}